I would like to thank Brandon Hanson, Giorgis Petridis, and Kevin Ford for helpful contributions to this post.
A well-known problem of Sárközy is the following.
Conjecture 1: Let
be a prime and
be the set of squares. Suppose
. Then either
or
.

As the squares are a multiplicative subgroup, it is natural to guess they cannot be written additively as a sumet. Conjecture 1 is in a similar spirit of a long list of conjectures concerning the independence of multiplication and addition, such as the twin prime conjecture, the abc-conjecture, and the sum-product conjecture.
Progress towards Conjecture 1, as of last week, was summarized in this mathoverflow post and this other mathoverflow post (and the papers referenced within). Sárközy proved that if
, then

which we recall below. In fact, Shparlinski (in Theorem 7) improved (1) and then later Shkredov showed (in Corollary 2.6)

Brandon Hanson and Giorgis Petridis, utilizing the polynomial method, recently made significant progress towards Conjecture 1.
Theorem 1 (Hanson-Petridis): Suppose
. Then

In particular every element of
has a unique representation of the form


Their techniques handle the case where
is replaced by any nontrivial multiplicative subgroup, but we focus on the squares for simplicity. In particular, if
is a prime, then Conjecture 1 is established. This implies Conjecture 1 is true for infinitely many primes, provided there are infinitely many Sophie Germain primes (yet another conjecture based on the independence of multiplication and addition). Making use of (1) we are able to prove this unconditionally. Here
is the prime counting function.
Corollary 1: For all but
primes less than
, Conjecture 1 holds.

Proof: Let
be a prime. Suppose
with
. Then by Theorem 1 and (1),
has a divisor between
and
. By Theorem 6 (followed by Theorem 1 (v)) in Kevin Ford’s work on the distribution of integers with divisors in an given interval, there are at most
such primes. Corollary 1 then follows from the prime number theorem.

If
, we always have trivial bound

which can be compared to the following bilinear estimate.
Theorem 2: Let
be the quadratic character modulo
. Then

In particular if
, then


The proof of Theorem 2, which we give, is standard Fourier manipulations (see chapter 4 of Tao and Vu for more details). As we will see below, Hanson and Petridis make no use of this perspective.
Proof: The second statement follows from the first as if
, then

By Fourier inversion, it is enough to show

where

Note
, and the usual estimate for Gauss sums implies

Combining with (3), it is enough to show

But this follows from Cauchy-Schwarz and Parseval.

Combining (2) and Theorem 2, we see that if
, then

Thus Theorem 1 asserts that the lower bound in (4) is the only possibility. We now proceed towards a proof of Theorem 1. The starting point is a classical theorem of Fermat.
Theorem 3 (Fermat): Let
. Then
if and only if
is a root of
.

There are many proofs of this elementary fact, for instance it is a quick consequence of Lagrange’s theorem. As a consequence, we have the following.
Corollary 2: Let
. Then
is a square if and only if
is a root to


Proof: Every square is a root of (5) as if
for some nonzero
then by Theorem 3,

Thus the squares are a subset of the roots of (5). On the other hand there are
squares and at most
roots and so the set of squares is precisely the set of roots of (5). 
In is worth noting that there is a significant gap in the degree of the polynomial in (5) as opposed to in Theorem 3, which we make use of later. We now give a polynomial characterization of the cardinality of a set.
Lemma 1: Let
and
. Then
if and only if for any
, the equations

have a solution in the
.

Proof: This is a classical fact about Vandermonde matrices.

We now proceed to the proof of Theorem 1, which adopts the Stepanov method of auxiliary polynomials.
Proof of Theorem 1: Let
and suppose
. We choose
, which is possible in light of (4). By Lemma 1, we may choose
so that
, where

Let

Our choice of
will ensure that each
is a root of
with high multiplicity and that
. By Corollary 2, since
,

Thus each
is a root of (7). Furthermore,

and so, again by Corollary 2,

We may apply this argument for higher derivatives to obtain

Thus each
is a root of
with multiplicity
and it follows that, if
,

It turns out that our previous choice for
ensure that
(and is thus nonzero). For instance, since
, considering the leading term in (6), we have

and so the leading term of
, which is the same, is also zero. The same argument works to show that the coefficient of
of
is zero for
. Now the constant term of
in (6) is

where is the coefficient of the
term in
is

Combining this with (8), we find

The second assertion in the Theorem follows immediately (see also Proposition 2.3 in Tao and Vu).

Remark 1: Suppose
with
. The proof of Theorem 1 reveals that

with
and
defined (7). Furthermore, we have the identity


A close variant of the extremal case left by Theorem 1 was studied by Lev and Sonn. Following Sárközy, we now prove (1) (with little concern for the precise constants). The key input is the Weil bounds, and so the square root barrier that appears in (1) is natural (as discussed in this previous blog post).
Proof of (1): Let
be a prime and suppose
. Without loss of generality, we may suppose
. By (2), it is enough to show

Let
be the Legendre symbol and consider, for
,

Thus
and by our assumption
for any
and so

On the other hand, expanding the product in (10) and applying the Weil bounds of the form

for distinct
, we find

This establishes (9) if
, since then we may choose
. Otherwise, we apply (12) with
and multiply both sides by
, and using (2), we find

This implies, crudely, that for
,

which is absurd for
large (and letting the implied constants handle the case
small). 